by Massimo Pigliucci
Saturday, December 29, 2012
Science and metaphysics
by Massimo Pigliucci
The philosophy of genetic drift
by Massimo Pigliucci
Friday, December 28, 2012
From the APA: Metaethical antirealism, evolution and genetic determinism
by Massimo Pigliucci
From the APA: Philosophers and climate change
by Massimo Pigliucci
Friday, December 21, 2012
Lakatos Award for Wolfgang Spohn
The London School of Economics and Political Science announces that the Lakatos Award, of £10,000 for an outstanding contribution to the philosophy of science, has been won by Wolfgang Spohn of the University of Konstanz for his book The Laws of Belief: Ranking Theory and its Philosophical Implications (Oxford University Press, 2012).
The Lakatos Award is given for an outstanding contribution to the philosophy of science, widely interpreted, in the form of a book published in English during the previous five years. It was made possible by a generous endowment from the Latsis Foundation. The Award is in memory of the former LSE professor, Imre Lakatos, and is administered by an international Management Committee organised from the LSE.
The Committee, chaired by John Worrall, decides the outcome of the Award competition on the advice of an international, independent and anonymous panel of Selectors who produce detailed reports on the nominated books.
________________________________________________________________________
Nominations can now be made for the 2013 Lakatos Award, and must be received by Friday 19th April 2013. The 2013 Award will be for a book published in English with an imprint from 2008-2013 inclusive. A book may, with the permission of the author, be nominated by any person of recognised standing within the profession. (The Management Committee is not empowered to nominate books itself but only to respond to outside nominations.)
For further details of the nomination procedure or more information on the Lakatos Award 2013, contact the Administrator, Tom Hinrichsen, at t.a.hinrichsen@lse.ac.uk
The Lakatos Award is given for an outstanding contribution to the philosophy of science, widely interpreted, in the form of a book published in English during the previous five years. It was made possible by a generous endowment from the Latsis Foundation. The Award is in memory of the former LSE professor, Imre Lakatos, and is administered by an international Management Committee organised from the LSE.
The Committee, chaired by John Worrall, decides the outcome of the Award competition on the advice of an international, independent and anonymous panel of Selectors who produce detailed reports on the nominated books.
________________________________________________________________________
Nominations can now be made for the 2013 Lakatos Award, and must be received by Friday 19th April 2013. The 2013 Award will be for a book published in English with an imprint from 2008-2013 inclusive. A book may, with the permission of the author, be nominated by any person of recognised standing within the profession. (The Management Committee is not empowered to nominate books itself but only to respond to outside nominations.)
For further details of the nomination procedure or more information on the Lakatos Award 2013, contact the Administrator, Tom Hinrichsen, at t.a.hinrichsen@lse.ac.uk
Monday, December 17, 2012
CfP for the 11th Graduate Conference at the University of Western Ontario
The University of Western Ontario is organizing its 11th Graduate Conference in Philosophy of Mind, Language, and Cognitive Science (May 23-25, 2013). The Call for Paper can be found there. The Deadline is March 1, 2013.
Friday, December 14, 2012
Conf: Evolution, Intentionality and Information (Bristol, May 2013)
Conference: Evolution, Intentionality and Information.
University of Bristol, May 29th-31st 2013.
A three-day inter-disciplinary conference at the University of Bristol.
This is the inaugural event in the ERC-funded project 'Darwinism and the
Theory of Rational Choice', directed by Professor Samir Okasha. The aim of the conference is to discuss the use of 'intentional', 'strategic' and 'informational' concepts in evolutionary biology.
Plenary speakers: Evelyn Fox-Keller, Daniel Dennett, Joan Roughgarden, Eva
Jablonka, David Haig, Denis Noble, Ken Binmore, Samir Okasha
Contributed papers are welcome.
For further information and details of how to register, please see the conference website.
Monday, December 10, 2012
Fellowships: Philosophy of Science (Pittsburgh)
The application deadline of December 15 is approaching for senior,
postdoctoral, and visiting fellowships at the Center for Philosophy of
Science, University of Pittsburgh, for the academic year 2013-2014.
For more details, see joining on the Center Web site (http://www.pitt.edu/~pittcntr).
For more details, see joining on the Center Web site (http://www.pitt.edu/~pittcntr).
Monday, November 26, 2012
Job: Postdoc AOS: Metaphysics of Science (IHPST, Paris)
A postdoctoral position will be available at IHPST (Institut d'Histoire
et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques, Paris) within the
French ANR funded project “Metaphysics of Science”, for one year
(September/October 2013 - August/September 2014), renewable for a second
year (September/October 2014 - August/September 2015).
The successful candidate must pursue research, and already have some expertise, in at least one of the three domains in the focus of the project: 1) Levels of reality, 2) Individual objects in physics and biology, and 3) Dispositions in psychology and physics.
The post-doc will be expected to present his/her research at conferences and seminars, and to publish in peer-reviewed journals.
He or she will work at IHPST in Paris and will provide organizational support for the activities of the teams. Residence in Paris is strictly mandatory.
Major tasks will be to:
1) run the Metaphysics of Science seminar on a regular basis,
2) help organize the workshops of the research project,
3) create and maintain a website on the metaphysics of experimental sciences, which will provide tools of cooperation within the team and help disseminate the results of our research,
4) constitute a database on metaphysics of science.
Applicants must have a doctorate in philosophy. Knowledge of French is not required, but fluency in English is.
Salary will be approximately 2000 € net (2500 € gross) per month.
Application material:
-A cover letter addressed to Max Kistler, Metascience coordinator
-A CV with a list of publications
-A writing sample (e.g., a publication or a dissertation chapter)
-Three letters of recommendation
-A statement of research agenda that fits into one of the areas of the project (2-3 pages)
Applications should be submitted electronically, in a single PDF file, to:
Max Kistler: mkistler@univ-paris1. fr
Deadline for submission of application: 15 February 2013.
Candidates will be informed of the decision by 31 March 2013.
For further information, please contact Max Kistler.
The successful candidate must pursue research, and already have some expertise, in at least one of the three domains in the focus of the project: 1) Levels of reality, 2) Individual objects in physics and biology, and 3) Dispositions in psychology and physics.
The post-doc will be expected to present his/her research at conferences and seminars, and to publish in peer-reviewed journals.
He or she will work at IHPST in Paris and will provide organizational support for the activities of the teams. Residence in Paris is strictly mandatory.
Major tasks will be to:
1) run the Metaphysics of Science seminar on a regular basis,
2) help organize the workshops of the research project,
3) create and maintain a website on the metaphysics of experimental sciences, which will provide tools of cooperation within the team and help disseminate the results of our research,
4) constitute a database on metaphysics of science.
Applicants must have a doctorate in philosophy. Knowledge of French is not required, but fluency in English is.
Salary will be approximately 2000 € net (2500 € gross) per month.
Application material:
-A cover letter addressed to Max Kistler, Metascience coordinator
-A CV with a list of publications
-A writing sample (e.g., a publication or a dissertation chapter)
-Three letters of recommendation
-A statement of research agenda that fits into one of the areas of the project (2-3 pages)
Applications should be submitted electronically, in a single PDF file, to:
Max Kistler: mkistler@univ-paris1.
Deadline for submission of application: 15 February 2013.
Candidates will be informed of the decision by 31 March 2013.
For further information, please contact Max Kistler.
Job: Assistant Professor AOS: Philosophy of Physics (LMU Munich)
The Chair of Philosophy of Science at the Faculty of Philosophy,
Philosophy of Science and Study of Religion and the Munich Center for
Mathematical Philosophy (MCMP, http://www.mcmp.philosophie. uni-muenchen.de/index.html)
at LMU Munich seek applications for an Assistant Professorship in
Philosophy of Physics. The position is for three years with the
possibility of extension for another three years. The appointment will
be made within the German A13 salary scheme (under the assumption that
the civil service requirements are met), which means that one has the
rights and perks of a civil servant. The starting date is October 1,
2013.
The appointee will be expected (i) to do philosophical research in the philosophy of physics and to lead a research group in this field, (ii) to teach five hours a week in philosophy of physics and/or a related field, and (iii) to take on management tasks. The successful candidate will have a PhD in philosophy and some teaching experience.
Applications (including a cover letter that addresses, amongst others, one's academic background and research interests, a CV, a list of publications, a list of taught courses, a sample of written work of no more than 5000 words, and a description of a planned research project of 1000-1500 words) should be sent by email (ideally everything requested in one PDF document) to sabine.krueger@lrz.uni- muenchen.de
by December 10, 2012. Additionally, two confidential letters of
reference addressing the applicant's qualifications for academic
research should be sent to the same address from the referees directly.
Contact for informal inquiries: Professor Stephan Hartmann (Stephan.Hartmann@lrz.uni- muenchen.de)
The appointee will be expected (i) to do philosophical research in the philosophy of physics and to lead a research group in this field, (ii) to teach five hours a week in philosophy of physics and/or a related field, and (iii) to take on management tasks. The successful candidate will have a PhD in philosophy and some teaching experience.
Applications (including a cover letter that addresses, amongst others, one's academic background and research interests, a CV, a list of publications, a list of taught courses, a sample of written work of no more than 5000 words, and a description of a planned research project of 1000-1500 words) should be sent by email (ideally everything requested in one PDF document) to sabine.krueger@lrz.uni-
Contact for informal inquiries: Professor Stephan Hartmann (Stephan.Hartmann@lrz.uni-
Wednesday, October 31, 2012
CFP: Philosophy of the Social Sciences (Venice, September 2013)
THE EUROPEAN NETWORK FOR THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES & THE PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE ROUNDTABLE
Call for Papers:
First joint European/American Conference University of Venice Ca' Foscari
3-4 September, 2013
The European Network for the Philosophy of the Social Sciences and the Phil= osophy of Social Science Roundtable invite contributions to their first joi= nt conference. Contributions from all areas within the philosophy of the so= cial sciences, from both philosophers and social scientists, are encouraged= .
Keynote speakers:
* Cristina Bicchieri (University of Pennsylvania)
* Nancy Cartwright (University of Durham/ University of California San =
Diego)
Submissions:
* An abstract of no more than 1000 words suitably prepared for blind re=
viewing should be submitted electronically through the Easychair system at =
https://www.easychair.org/ conferences/?conf= 3Denpossrt2013. Only one abst= ract per person may be submitted.
* Deadline for submission: 27 January, 2013
* Date of notification of acceptance: 15 March, 2013
Local organizers:
* Eleonora Montuschi, Luigi Perissinotto (University of Venice Ca' Fosc=
ari, Dept. of Philosophy and Cultural Heritage, Philosophy Section).
Conference homepage:
For more information about the conference see www.enposs.eu<http://www.enpo= ss.eu>
Publication:
* Selected papers from the Conference will be published in an annual sp=
ecial issue of the journal Philosophy of the Social Sciences
ENPOSS:
The purpose of the European Network of Philosophy of the Social Sciences is= to promote, encourage and facilitate academic discussion and research in t= he philosophy of the social sciences broadly conceived.
Steering Committee: Alban Bouvier (Paris), Byron Kaldis (Athens), Thomas Ue= bel (Manchester), Julie Zahle (Copenhagen), and Jes=FAs Zamora-Bonilla (Mad= rid).
PSSRT:
The Philosophy of Social Science Roundtable serves as a forum for communica= tion among philosophers and social scientists who share an interest in disc= ussion of epistemology, explanatory paradigms, and methodologies of the soc= ial sciences.
Programme Committee: James Bohman (St. Louis), Mark Risjord (Atlanta), Paul= Roth (Santa Cruz), Stephen Turner (Tampa), Alison Wylie (Seattle)
Call for Papers:
First joint European/American Conference University of Venice Ca' Foscari
3-4 September, 2013
The European Network for the Philosophy of the Social Sciences and the Phil= osophy of Social Science Roundtable invite contributions to their first joi= nt conference. Contributions from all areas within the philosophy of the so= cial sciences, from both philosophers and social scientists, are encouraged= .
Keynote speakers:
* Cristina Bicchieri (University of Pennsylvania)
* Nancy Cartwright (University of Durham/ University of California San =
Diego)
Submissions:
* An abstract of no more than 1000 words suitably prepared for blind re=
viewing should be submitted electronically through the Easychair system at =
https://www.easychair.org/
* Deadline for submission: 27 January, 2013
* Date of notification of acceptance: 15 March, 2013
Local organizers:
* Eleonora Montuschi, Luigi Perissinotto (University of Venice Ca' Fosc=
ari, Dept. of Philosophy and Cultural Heritage, Philosophy Section).
Conference homepage:
For more information about the conference see www.enposs.eu<http://www.enpo= ss.eu>
Publication:
* Selected papers from the Conference will be published in an annual sp=
ecial issue of the journal Philosophy of the Social Sciences
ENPOSS:
The purpose of the European Network of Philosophy of the Social Sciences is= to promote, encourage and facilitate academic discussion and research in t= he philosophy of the social sciences broadly conceived.
Steering Committee: Alban Bouvier (Paris), Byron Kaldis (Athens), Thomas Ue= bel (Manchester), Julie Zahle (Copenhagen), and Jes=FAs Zamora-Bonilla (Mad= rid).
PSSRT:
The Philosophy of Social Science Roundtable serves as a forum for communica= tion among philosophers and social scientists who share an interest in disc= ussion of epistemology, explanatory paradigms, and methodologies of the soc= ial sciences.
Programme Committee: James Bohman (St. Louis), Mark Risjord (Atlanta), Paul= Roth (Santa Cruz), Stephen Turner (Tampa), Alison Wylie (Seattle)
Labels:
calls for papers,
news and announcements
Tuesday, October 30, 2012
CFP: Models and Decisions (Munich, April 2013)
***************************************
6th Munich-Sydney-Tilburg conference on
MODELS AND DECISIONS
Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy
10-12 April 2013
http://www.lmu.de/ModelsAndDec isions2013
****************************** **********
Mathematical and computational models are central to decision-making in a wide-variety of contexts in science and policy: They are used to assess the risk of large investments, to evaluate the merits of alternative medical therapies, and are often key in decisions on international policies – climate policy being one of the most prominent examples. In many of these cases, they assist in drawing conclusions
from complex assumptions. While the value of these models is undisputed, their increasingly widespread use raises several philosophical questions: What makes scientific models so important? In which way do they describe, or even explain their target systems? What makes models so reliable? And: What are the imports, and the limits, of using models in policy making? This conference will bring together philosophers of science, economists, statisticians and policy makers to discuss these
and related questions. Experts from a variety of field will exchange first-hand experience and insights in order to identify the assets and the pitfalls of model-based decision-making. The conference will also address and evaluate the increasing role of model-based research in scientific practice, both from a practical and from a philosophical point of view.
We invite submissions of extended abstracts of 1000 words by 15 December 2012. Decisions will be made by 15 January 2013.
KEYNOTE SPEAKERS: Luc Bovens (LSE), Itzhak Gilboa (Paris and Tel Aviv),
Ulrike Hahn (Birkbeck), Michael Strevens (NYU), and Claudia Tebaldi (UBC)
ORGANIZERS: Mark Colyvan, Paul Griffiths, Stephan Hartmann, Kaerin
Nickelsen, Roland Poellinger, Olivier Roy, and Jan Sprenger
PUBLICATION: We plan to publish selected papers presented at the
conference in a special issue of a journal or with a major a book
publisher (subject to the usual refereeing process). The submission
deadline is 1 July 2013. The maximal paper length is 7000 words.
GRADUATE FELLOWSHIPS: A few travel bursaries for graduate students are
available (up to 500 Euro). See the website for details.
MODELS AND DECISIONS
Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy
10-12 April 2013
http://www.lmu.de/ModelsAndDec
******************************
Mathematical and computational models are central to decision-making in a wide-variety of contexts in science and policy: They are used to assess the risk of large investments, to evaluate the merits of alternative medical therapies, and are often key in decisions on international policies – climate policy being one of the most prominent examples. In many of these cases, they assist in drawing conclusions
from complex assumptions. While the value of these models is undisputed, their increasingly widespread use raises several philosophical questions: What makes scientific models so important? In which way do they describe, or even explain their target systems? What makes models so reliable? And: What are the imports, and the limits, of using models in policy making? This conference will bring together philosophers of science, economists, statisticians and policy makers to discuss these
and related questions. Experts from a variety of field will exchange first-hand experience and insights in order to identify the assets and the pitfalls of model-based decision-making. The conference will also address and evaluate the increasing role of model-based research in scientific practice, both from a practical and from a philosophical point of view.
We invite submissions of extended abstracts of 1000 words by 15 December 2012. Decisions will be made by 15 January 2013.
KEYNOTE SPEAKERS: Luc Bovens (LSE), Itzhak Gilboa (Paris and Tel Aviv),
Ulrike Hahn (Birkbeck), Michael Strevens (NYU), and Claudia Tebaldi (UBC)
ORGANIZERS: Mark Colyvan, Paul Griffiths, Stephan Hartmann, Kaerin
Nickelsen, Roland Poellinger, Olivier Roy, and Jan Sprenger
PUBLICATION: We plan to publish selected papers presented at the
conference in a special issue of a journal or with a major a book
publisher (subject to the usual refereeing process). The submission
deadline is 1 July 2013. The maximal paper length is 7000 words.
GRADUATE FELLOWSHIPS: A few travel bursaries for graduate students are
available (up to 500 Euro). See the website for details.
Labels:
calls for papers,
news and announcements
Special Issue: Kuhnian Perspectives on the Life and Human SciencesSCIENCES
To mark the 50th anniversary of the publication of Thomas Kuhn's The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions, a Kuhn-and-revolutions-themed
special issue of articles from Studies in History and Philosophy of
Biological and Biomedical Sciences is now available for free downloading
at the journal's website:
http://www.journals.elsevier. com/studies-in-history-and- philosophy-of-science-part-c- studies-in-history-and- philosophy-of-biological-and- biomedical-sciences/
In the main journal, articles from the current (September 2012) issue include:
* Anna Maerker on Florentine anatomical wax models in eighteenth-century Vienna
* Roberta Millstein on Darwin, race and sexual selection
* Leon Rocha on Needham, Daoism and Science and Civilization in China
http://www.journals.elsevier.
In the main journal, articles from the current (September 2012) issue include:
* Anna Maerker on Florentine anatomical wax models in eighteenth-century Vienna
* Roberta Millstein on Darwin, race and sexual selection
* Leon Rocha on Needham, Daoism and Science and Civilization in China
Monday, October 29, 2012
From the naturalism workshop, part III
And we have now arrived at the commentary on the final day of the workshop on “Moving Naturalism forward,” organized by cosmologist Sean Carroll. It was my tun to do an introductory presentation on the relationship between science and philosophy, and on the idea of scientism. (Part I of this commentary is here, part II here.)
I began by pointing out that it doesn’t help anyone if we play semantic games with terms like “science” and “philosophy.” In particular, “science” cannot be taken to be simply whatever deals with facts, just like “philosophy” isn’t whatever deals with thinking. So for instance, facts about the planets in the solar system are scientific facts, but the observation that I live in Manhattan near the Queensborough Bridge is just a fact, science has nothing to do with it. Similarly, John Rawls’ book A Theory of Justice, to pick an arbitrary example, is real philosophy, while Ron Hubbard’s nonsense about Dianetics isn’t, even though he thought of it as such.
So science becomes a particular type of structured social activity, characterized by empirically driven hypothesis testing about the way the world works, peer review, technical journals, and so on. And philosophy is about deploying logic and general tools of reasoning and argument to reflect on a broad range of subject matters (epistemology, ethics, aesthetics, etc.) and to reflect on other disciplines (“philosophies of”).
Another important thing to get straight: philosophy is not in the business of advancing science. We’ve got science for that, and it works very well. Some philosophy is “continuous” with science, but most is not. Also, philosophy makes progress by exploring logical space, not by making empirical discoveries.
I then brought up the Bad Boy of physics, Richard Feynman, who famously said: “Philosophy of science is about as useful to scientists as ornithology is to birds.” True enough (except when it comes to ornithologists helping out avoiding the extinction of some bird species), but surely that does not imply that ornithology is thereby useless.
Next, I moved to a discussion of scientism. I suggested that in the strong sense this is the view that only scientific claims, or only questions that can be addressed by science, are meaningful. In a weaker sense, it is the view that the methods of the natural sciences can and should be applied to any subject matter. I think the first one is indefensible, and that the second one needs to be qualified and circumscribed. For instance, there are plenty of areas where science has little or nothing interesting to say: mathematics, logic, aesthetics, ethics, literature, just to name a few.
It is, of course, true that a number of philosophers have said, and continue to say, bizarro things about science, or even about philosophy itself (Thomas Nagel and Jerry Fodor come to mind as recent examples). But a pretty good number of scientists are on record has having said bizarro things about philosophy, or even about science itself (Lawrence Krauss, and more recently Freeman Dyson).
What I suggested as a way forward is that we should work toward re-establishing the classical notion of scientia, which means knowledge in the broader sense, including contributions from science, philosophy, math, and logic. There is also an even broader concept of understanding, which is relevant to human affairs. And I think that understanding requires not only scientia, but also other human activities such as art, music, literature, and the broader humanities. As you can see, I was trying to be very ecumenical...
In the end, I submitted that skirmishes between scientists and philosophers are not just badly informed and somewhat silly, they are anti-intellectual, and do not help the common cause of moving society toward a more rational and compassionate state than it finds itself in now.
The discussion that followed was very interesting. Alex Rosenberg did stress that philosophers interested in science need to pay close attention to what goes on in the lab, to which both Sean Carroll and Janna Levin responded that there are very good examples of important conceptual contributions made by philosophers to physics, particularly in the area of interpretations of quantum mechanics. Rosenberg also pointed out that some philosophers — for instance Samir Okasha — have contributed to biology, for instance in the area of debates about levels of selection.
We then talked about the issue of division of intellectual labor, with Dennett stressing the ability (and dangers!) of philosophers to take a bird’s eye view of things that is often unavailable to scientists. This, I commented, is because scientists are justifiably busy with writing grant proposals, doing lab work, and interacting tightly with graduate students. That was my own experience as a practicing evolutionary biologist. As a philosopher, I rarely write grant proposals, I don’t have to run a lab or do field work, and my interactions with graduate students are often in the form of visits to coffee houses and wine bars. All of which affords me the “luxury” (really, it’s my job) to read, think and write more broadly now than what I could do when I was a practicing scientist.
Along similar lines, Sean Carroll remarked — again going back to actual examples from physics — that scientists concern themselves primarily with how to figure things out, postponing the broader question of what those things mean. That’s another area where good philosophy can be helpful. Rebecca Goldstein added that philosophy is hard to do well, and that scientists should be more respectful and less dismissive of what philosophers do. Janna Levin observed that much of the fracas in this area is caused by a few prominent, senior (quasi-senile?) scientists and philosophers, but that in reality most scientists have a healthy degree of respect for philosophy.
At this point Coyne asked a reasonable question: we have talked about contributions that philosophers have made to science, what about the other way around? Several people offered the examples of Einstein, Bell and Feynman (ironically, the same guy of the philosophy-as-ornithology comment mentioned above), the latter for instance on the concept of natural law.
That was it, folks. What did I take from the experience? At the least the following points:
* On naturalism in general: we agreed that there are different shades of philosophical naturalism, and that reasonable people may disagree about the degree of, say, reductionism or determinism that the view entails.
* On determinism: given that even the physicists aren’t sure, yet, whether quantum mechanics is best interpreted deterministically or not (not to mention of the interpretation of any more fundamental theory), the question is open.
* On reductionism: Rosenberg’s extreme reductionism-nihilism was clearly, well, extreme within this group. Most participants agreed that one can, indeed should, still talk about morality and responsibility in meaningful terms.
* On emergence: there was, predictably, disagreement here, even among the physicists. Carroll seemed the most sympathetic to the concept, repeatedly talking, for instance, about the emergence of the Second Law of thermodynamics from statistical mechanics. Even Weinberg agreed that there are emergent phenomena in a robust sense of the term, but of course he preferred a “weak” concept of emergence, according to which the reductionist can write a promissory note that “in principle” things could be explained by a fundamental law. It was unclear what such principle may be, or even why that fundamental law couldn’t itself be considered emergent from something else (the “it’s turtles all the way down” problem).
* On meaning: following Goldstein, most of us agreed that there is meaning in human life, which comes out of the sense that we matter in society and to our fellow human beings. Flanagan’s concept of “eudaimonics” was, I think, most helpful here.
* On free will and moral responsibility: the debate between incompatibilists (Coyne, Rosenberg) and compatibilists (most of the rest, led of course by Dennett) continued. But we agreed that “free will” is far too loaded a concept, with Flanagan’s suggestion that we go back to the ancient Greeks’ categories of voluntary and involuntary action being particularly useful, I think. Even Coyne agreed that there is a Dennett-like sense in which we can think of morally competent vs morally incompetent agents (say, a normal person and one with a brain tumor affecting his behavior), thereby rescuing a societally and legally relevant concept of morality and responsibility.
* Relationship between science and philosophy: people seemed in broad agreement with my presentation (again, including Jerry), from which it follows that science and philosophy are partially continuous and partially independent disciplines, the first one focused on the systematic study of empirical data about the world, the second more concerned with conceptual clarification and meta-analysis (“philosophy of”). We also agreed that there are indeed good examples of philosophers of science playing a constructive role in science, and vice versa of scientists who have contributed to philosophy of science (take that, Krauss and Hawking!).
This, added to the positive effect of meeting one’s intellectual adversaries in person, sharing meals and talking over a beer or a glass of wine, has definitely made a stupendous success of the workshop as a whole. Stay tuned for the full video version on YouTube...
Saturday, October 27, 2012
From the naturalism workshop, part II
by Massimo Pigliucci
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)